In 1982, when Bladerunner was
released, 2019 could only have been a blink of an eye in people’s thoughts.
Even the year 2001, the year in which the movie 2001: A Space Odessey (1968)
takes place, must have seemed far off. Of course, the actual year was not so futuristic
as to have a computer take over a space station; controversy over AI eclipsing the
grasp of human control would not hit the societal mainstream for twenty years. So, Ridley Scott can hardly be blamed for positing
flying cars, and, even more astonishing, imposing the notion of a replicant, a
being of genetic biomechanics that fuses computer and human characteristics, on
2019. Even acknowledging the tremendous impacts on society of inventions since
the dawn of the twentieth century, the pace of technological change is slower
than we imagine. In 2019, on the cusp of a global pandemic, flying (and
self-driving) cars were just in the prototype/testing phase, and AI existed rudimentarily,
and certainly not corporeally in human form. Scott missed the mark, probably by
decades, though he got the trajectory right. Indeed, the film’s central issue—that
of the threat of run-away, or “rebellious,” AI to humans—was reflected in the
press especially during the first half of 2023. I contend, however, that the
philosophical merit of the film lies not in political theory, but, rather, in
what it means to be human. The nature of human understanding, self-awareness,
an ethical sense, and matters of theological reflection are all brought to the
forefront in the question of whether the replicants can and should be taken as human
beings. In other words, it is the fusion of AI, or computers more generally,
and biology that lies at the core of the film.
In the film, Deckard is hired to
kill replicants who have rebelled by traveling to Earth. His character arc can
be grasped in terms of a gradual recognition that they essentially human, or at
least enough like us that they can and should be regarded as subjects rather
than objects. The film furnishes us with several criteria in which the
replicants can be counted as human.
Self-awareness
is the foremost criterion: taking oneself to be an entity that has
subjectivity. At one point in the film, Pris, a female replicant, says, “I
think, therefore I am.” Cogito ergo sum. The screenwriter doubtlessly
had Descartes in mind. I am aware that I am thinking, therefore I exist. Even
if an evil deceiver has us believing incorrectly that the world of appearances
exists, we know that our thinking does not depend on any external world. In the
film, the replicants can indeed think; they have been programmed to do so by
Tyrell, who is a genius. In fact, the leader of the rebel replicants on Earth,
Batty, refers to Tyrell as the replicant’s creator (god) even though it could
be argued that the genetic bioengineers who grow the biological organs of the
replicants also warrant such divine status. In actuality, there is nothing divine
about programming AI or growing biological organs presumably out of stem-cells.
It is not as if Tyrell and his engineers create everything, whether ex
nihilo or not (one of the Creation accounts in Genesis is not ex
nihilo). In other words, the give rise to existence itself is qualitatively
different than creating something in particular in the realm of
already-existence.
So the
replicants have the human attribute of being self-conscious of themselves as
entities that can think. This is not to say that they are minds in vats filled
with chemicals. Pris insists that she is also physical, by which she means
biological or corporeal in nature. She has a body; a replicant has biomass and
even human genes. One of the biometric engineers tells a replicant, “You have
my genes in you.” Can we say then that Descartes’ mind/body duality pertains to
replicants? The replicant’s mind is programmed whereas the bodies are grown
organically. The film does not provide us with a definite account of how the
replicant brain is “hard-wired”—whether it is a computer physically emmeshed in
a biological body or that computer code has somehow been written into the
organic neuro-networks. The latter alternative lies beyond our comprehension,
at least as of 2023. Indeed, it may even seem paradoxical. In a Gospel
narrative, the risen Jesus walks through a door yet he is hungry and eats a
fish. It is clear that his corporeal body has been transformed yet is still corporeal.
In Pris insisting to the bioengineer who grows eyes using his own genes for
replicants that she is physical rather than merely a thinking thing, the
implication is that the replicants are entirely biological (i.e., every organ
is organic rather than machine). Yet in her death throws after being shot (not
tased!), Pris’s body shakes violently as if it were being electrocuted. The implication
here is that her brain was hit and is electronic circuits rather than made of
flesh. If so, it is remarkable, again from the standpoint of the actual world
in 2023, that a hard-wire computer can have self-awareness, and thus be taken
as a subject (i.e., having subjectivity).
Furthermore,
the replicants have emotions, which are in the subjectivity; that is, the replicants
know that they themselves feel. The replicants, especially Batty being of the
sixth generation, are intelligent. So too is Tyrell, who had programmed Batty;
both are superb at the game of chess. The replicants know that they (i.e.,
their respective subjectivities) will one day come to an end. In being mortal,
they are like us. Similarly, they fear death. Two replicants, one of whom is
Batty, make it clear that they fear dying. Batty even tells Deckard, the
bladerunner, that it is precisely that fear that makes someone a slave—a slave
to one’s fear. So it is clear that AI extends in the story-world of the film beyond
intelligence to include emotions. Additionally, Batty clearly mourns Pris, and even
exacts vengeance on Deckard for having killed Pris and another replicant in
Batty’s rebel group.
Even more astonishingly, the AI
manifesting in Batty includes a moral sense. When Tyrell tells Batty, “You’re
the prodigal son,” Batty retorts, “I’ve done questionable things.” Ironically,
it is the human Tyrell who seems to be missing the moral sense, for he replies,
“Also extraordinary things!” It is indeed extraordinary that a replicant would
then bring in theology in saying quite sadly, “Nothing that the god of
biomechanics would let you into heaven for.” Batty even conceptualizes heaven.
At one point while fighting Deckard, Batty says, “Go to hell; go to heaven.”
Batty’s sarcastic quip, “Aren’t you the good man” to Deckard for not fighting
fair, can be assumed to have theological and not merely moral overtones. Batty
even calls him a bastard spirit. Finally, clearly aware that he is soon going
to die, Batty saves Deckard rather than kills him. Kindness to one’s enemy has
explicit religious overtones in Christianity even if most Christians prefer to focus
instead on a metaphysical belief-claim that is only indirectly linked to
helping one’s enemies. Indeed, the history of Christianity presents examples of
Christians having “true belief” yet belying the claim by persecuting rather
than helping people they didn’t like. Here in Bladerunner, it is a replicant
that ironically provides us with an illustrative example of Christian charity.
Deckard can only look up perplexed at Batty’s change of heart. When Batty dies,
he releases a white dove, which flies away, evocative perhaps of Batty’s soul
leaving his body. At the very least, Batty has in his mind the idea of God. In
his proof that God exists, Descartes posits that existence because the idea, itself
having full perfection, could not come from a being of less perfection. So God
must exist for there to be the idea of God in a human mind. Yet a finite mind can
also have the idea of infinity without there even needing to be infinity.
At the very least, it is clear
that Batty thinks a lot about morality and even religion. In contrast, Deckard
does not. Even though Batty has done “questionable things,” it is telling that he
is quite aware of this. Historically, Shaftsbury, Hutcheson, Hume, and Adam
Smith all posited a moral sentiment in human nature; we are fundamentally
sociable creatures who gain pleasure from shared experience that “fellow
feeling,” or sympathy, and imagination can provide. When Batty saves Deckard
from falling, the two share an intimate moment emotionally as Batty shares the
marvels of what he has seen. He is
saying, in effect, that he had not been merely an instrument, or object, that
humans sent out to protect the colonies in space; rather, his existence has
chiefly been that of a subjectivity, and is thus worthy of being taken as an
end in itself, rather than merely as a means to a human’s plans. Kant’s ethical
claim that beings partaking in rational nature—being able to use reasoning—should
be valued in themselves is taken up and embraced implicitly by the most
advanced replicant. As he was being used as an instrument—an object—to protect
the intergalactic colonies, Batty was marveling at the sights. He was not
merely a machine. Perhaps by observing the humanity of the dying replicant, Deckard
then comes to the realization that he loves Rachael, one of the female replicants,
and that she can love and trust him. The two recognize each other as subjects—each
as having a subjectivity rather than being taken as an object.
In short, the film essentially asks what it means to be human. Self-awareness, reasoning, emotions, a moral sense, and even contemplation of ideas transcending the limits of human conception and perception are qualities that pertain to at least the most advanced generation of replicants. It is ironic that it is a replicant, Batty, who brings up and critiques Deckard from moral and religious standpoints. Clearly, a replicant’s understanding goes beyond the machine-type of “manipulation of symbols according to rules.” Moreover, the cognition and understanding mesh with emotions and self-awareness, as well as the awareness of other subjects. Indeed, the aforementioned qualities of the replicants are sufficient to support the claim that they can love and be loved in return—the Bohemian ideal expressed in Moulin Rouge.
In Bladerunner, both Deckard and
Batty come around to being more human, and thus more humane. Both can be taken
as subjects rather than objects; both have subjectivities. Perhaps it can even
be said that Deckard’s humanity depends on that of the replicants, or at least
to the recognition that they are sufficiently human to be taken as such rather
than as walking computers. Certainly, it is the humaneness of Batty that
Deckard literally comes to depend on to live another day. It certainly would not make
sense to say that Deckard owes anything to the replicant were it merely
a machine that manipulates symbols according to rules even assuming the existence
of machine learning. Yet that Batty has a subjectivity and thus experience that
goes beyond his essence—an existentialist assumption—means that Deckard can
feel that he owes Batty a debt of gratitude. Certainly Deckard feels an ethical
obligation toward Rachael because she not only loves him, but trusts him as
well. She is thus capable of being hurt emotionally, should he betray her by
reverting back to viewing the replicants as objects. Finally we have in Bladerunner
what it means to be human, ironically in its fullest sense.